MCLC: critique of 'tale of two political systems'

Denton, Kirk denton.2 at osu.edu
Mon Jul 8 09:41:13 EDT 2013


MCLC LIST
From: pjmooney <pjmooney at me.com>
Subject: critique of 'tale of two political systems'
***********************************************************

Source: TED (7/1/13):
http://blog.ted.com/2013/07/01/why-democracy-still-wins-a-critique-of-eric-
x-lis-a-tale-of-two-political-systems/

Why democracy still wins: A critique of Eric X. Li’s “A tale of two
political systems”
By Yasheng Huang

Earlier this year, economist Yasheng Huang (watch his 2011 TED Talk
<http://www.ted.com/talks/yasheng_huang.html>) sparred with Eric X. Li in
the pages of Foreign Affairs on a similar topic
<http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/138476/eric-x-li/the-life-of-the-pa
rty> to today’s TED Talk. The TED Blog asked Huang to expand on his
argument in his ongoing conversation with Li.

Eric X. Li: A tale of two political systems
<http://www.ted.com/talks/eric_x_li_a_tale_of_two_political_systems.html>

Imagine confusing the following two statements from a cancer doctor: 1)
“You may die from cancer” and 2) “I want you to die from cancer.” It is
not hard to see a rudimentary difference between these two statements. The
first statement is a prediction — it is saying that something may happen
given certain conditions (in this case death conditional upon having
cancer). The second statement is a preference, a desire, or a wish for a
world to one’s particular liking.

Who would make such a rudimentary mistake confusing these two types of
statements? Many people, including Eric X. Li, in today’s TED Talk.
The Marxian meta-narrative drilled into Li’s head — and mine in my
childhood and youth in the 1960s and 1970s — is a normative statement.
When Marx came up with his ideas about evolution of human societies, there
was not a single country in the world that even remotely resembled the
communist system he advocated. The communist system Marx had in mind had
no private property or of ownership of any kind. Money was also absent in
that system. The Marxian version of communism has never come to fruition
and, most likely, never will. Marx based his “prediction” on deduction;
his successors did so by imposing their wish, enforced by power and
violence.

By contrast, the narrative that was apparently fed to Li when he was a
“Berkeley hippie” is based on the actual experience of human affairs. We
have had hundreds of years of experience with democracy and hundreds of
countries/years of democratic transitions and rule. The statement that
countries transition to democracy as they get rich is a positive statement
— it is a prediction based on data. In the 1960s, roughly 25 percent  of
the world was democratic; today the proportion is 63 percent. There are
far more instances of dictatorships transitioning to democracies  than the
other way around. The rest of the world has clearly expressed a preference
for democracy. As Minxin Pei has pointed out, of the 25 countries with a
higher GDP per capita than China that are not free or partially free, 21
of them are sustained by natural resources. But these are exceptions that
prove the rule — countries become democratic as they get richer. Today not
a single country classified as the richest is a single-party authoritarian
system. (Singapore is arguably a borderline case.) Whether Li likes it or
not, they all seem to end up in the same place.

Are democracies more corrupt? Li thinks so. He cites the Transparency
International (TI) index
<http://www.transparency.org/research/cpi/overview> to support his view.
The TI data show that China is ranked better than many democracies. Fair
enough.

I have always thought that there is a touch of irony with using
transparency data to defend a political system built on opacity. Irony
aside, let’s keep in mind that TI index itself is a product of a political
system that Li so disparages — democracy (German democracy to be exact).
This underscores a basic point — we know far more about corruption in
democracies than we do about corruption in authoritarian countries because
democracies are, by definition, more transparent and they have more
transparency data. While I trust comparisons of corruption among
democratic countries, to mechanically compare corruption in China with
that in democracies, as Li has done so repeatedly, is fundamentally
flawed. His methodology confounds two effects — how transparent a country
is and how corrupt a country is. I am not saying that democracies are
necessarily cleaner than China; I am just saying that Li’s use of TI data
is not the basis for drawing conclusions in either direction. The right
way to reach a conclusion on this issue is to say that given the same
level of transparency (and the same level of many other things, including
income), China is — or is not — more corrupt than democracies.

A simple example will suffice to illustrate this idea. In 2010, two Indian
entrepreneurs founded a website called I Paid a Bribe
<http://www.ipaidabribe.com/>. The website invited anonymous postings of
instances in which Indian citizens had to pay a bribe. By August 2012 the
website has recorded more than 20,000 reports of corruption. Some Chinese
entrepreneurs tried to do the same thing: They created I Made a Bribe and
522phone.com <http://www.522phone.com/>. But those websites were promptly
shut down by the Chinese government. The right conclusion is not, as the
logic of Li would suggest, that China is cleaner than India because it has
zero postings of corrupt instances whereas India has some 20,000 posted
instances of corruption.

With due respect to the good work at Transparency International, its data
are very poor at handling this basic difference between perception of
corruption and incidence of corruption. Democracies are more transparent —
about its virtues and its vices — than authoritarian systems.  We know far
more about Indian corruption in part because the Indian system is more
transparent, and it has a noisy chattering class who are not afraid to
challenge and criticize the government (and, in a few instances, to stick
a video camera into a hotel room recording the transfer of cash to
politicians). Also lower-level corruption is more observable than
corruption at the top of the political hierarchy. The TI index is better
at uncovering the corruption of a Barun the policeman in Chennai than a Bo
Xilai the Politburo member from Chongqing. These factors, not corruption
per se, are likely to explain most of the discrepancies between China and
India in terms of TI rankings.

Li likes to point out, again using TI data, that the likes of Indonesia,
Argentina and the Philippines are both democracies and notoriously
corrupt. He often omits crucial factual details when he is addressing this
issue. Yes, these countries are democracies, in 2013, but they were
governed by ruthless military dictators for decades long before they
transitioned to democracy. It was the autocracy of these countries that
bred and fermented corruption. (Remember the 3,000 pairs of shoes of Mrs.
Marcos?) Corruption is like cancer, metastatic and entrenched. While it is
perfectly legitimate to criticize new democracies for not rooting out
corruption in a timely fashion, confusing the difficulties of treating the
entrenched corruption with its underlying cause is analogous to saying
that a cancer patient got his cancer after he was admitted for
chemotherapy.

The world league of the most egregious corruption offenders belongs
exclusively to autocrats. The top three ruling looters as of 2004,
according to a TI report, are Suharto, Marcos and Mobutu. These three
dictators pillaged a combined $50 billion from their impoverished people.
Democracies are certainly not immune to corruption, but I think that they
have to work a lot harder before they can catch up with these autocrats.

Li has a lot of faith in the Chinese system. He first argues that the
system enjoys widespread support among the Chinese population. He cites a
Financial Times survey that 93 percent
<http://survey.telefonica.com/connected-yet-divided-telefonica-survey-of-th
e-millennial-generation-reveals-digital-natives-are-optimistic-about-their-
individual-futures-despite-splits-across-political-economic-and-technology-
ou/> of Chinese young people are optimistic about their future. I have
seen these high approval ratings used by Li and others as evidence that
the Chinese system is healthy and robust, but I am puzzled why Li should
stop at 93 percent. Why not go further, to 100 percent ? In a country
without free speech, asking people to directly evaluate performance of
leaders is like asking people to take a single-choice exam. The poll
numbers for Erich Honecker and Kim Jong-un would put Chinese leaders to
shame.

(Let me also offer a cautionary footnote on how and how not to use Chinese
survey data. I have done a lot of survey research in China, and I am
always humbled by how tricky it is to interpret the survey findings. Apart
from the political pressures that tend to channel answers in a particular
direction, another problem is that Chinese respondents sometimes view
taking a survey as similar to taking an exam. Chinese exams have standard
answers, and sometimes Chinese respondents fill out surveys by trying to
guess what the “standard” answer is rather than expressing their own
views. I would caution against any naïve uses of Chinese survey data.)
Li also touts the adaptability of the Chinese political system. Let me
quote:

“Now, most political scientists will tell us that a one-party system is
inherently incapable of self-correction. It won’t last long because it
cannot adapt. Now here are the facts. In 64 years of running the largest
country in the world, the range of the party’s policies has been wider
than any other country in recent memory, from radical land
collectivization to the Great Leap Forward, then privatization of
farmland, then the Cultural Revolution, then Deng Xiaoping’s market
reform, then successor Jiang Zemin took the giant political step of
opening up party membership to private businesspeople, something
unimaginable during Mao’s rule. So the party self-corrects in rather
dramatic fashion.”

Now imagine putting forward the following narrative celebrating, say,
Russian “adaptability”: Russia, as a country or as a people, is highly
adaptable. The range of its “policies has been wider than any other
country in recent memory,” from gulags to Stalin’s red terror, then
collectivization, then central planning, then glasnost and perestroika,
then privatization, then crony capitalism, then the illiberal democracy
under Putin, something unimaginable during Lenin’s rule. So the country
“self-corrects in rather dramatic fashion.”
Let me be clear and explicit — Li’s reasoning on the adaptability of the
Chinese Communist Party (CCP) is exactly identical to the one I offered on
Russia. The only difference is that Li was referring to a political
organization — the CCP — and I am referring to a sovereign state.

The TED audience greeted Li’s speech with applause — several times in
fact. I doubt that had Li offered this Russian analogy the reception would
have been as warm. The reason is simple: The TED audience is intimately
familiar with the tumult, violence and astronomical human toll of the
Soviet rule. Steven Pinker
<http://www.ted.com/talks/steven_pinker_on_the_myth_of_violence.html>, in
his book The Better Angels of Our Nature, quoted the findings by other
scholars that the Soviet regime killed 62 million of its own citizens. I
guess the word “correction” somewhat understates the magnitude of the
transformation from Stalin’s murderous, genocidal regime to the
problematic, struggling but nonetheless democratic Russia today.

I do not know what a Berkeley hippie learned from his education, but in
Cambridge, Massachusetts, where I received my education and where I am a
professor by profession, I learned — and teach — every day that words
actually have meaning. To me, self-correction implies at least two things.
First, a self-correction is, well, a correction by self. Yes, Mao’s
policies were “corrected” or even reversed by his successors, as Li
pointed out, but in what sense is this “a self-correction?” Mao’s utterly
disastrous policies persisted during his waning days even while the
chairman lay in a vegetative state and his successor — who came to power
through a virtual coup — only dared to modify Mao’s policies after his
physical expiration was certain. If this is an instance of
self-correction, exactly what is not a self-correction? Almost every
single policy change Li identified in his talk was made by the successor
to the person who initiated the policy that got corrected. (In quite a few
cases, not even by the immediate successor.) This is a bizarre definition
of self-correction. Does it constitute a self-correction when the math
errors I left uncorrected in my childhood are now being corrected by my
children?

The second meaning of self-correction has to do with the circumstances in
which the correction occurs, not just the identity of the person making
the correction. A 10-year-old can correct her spelling or math error on
her own volition, or she could have done so after her teacher registered a
few harsh slaps on the back of her left hand. In both situations the
identity of the corrector is the same — the 10-year-old student — but the
circumstances of the correction are vastly different. One would normally
associate the first situation with “self-correction,” the second situation
with coercion, duress or, as in this case, violence. In other words,
self-correction implies a degree of voluntariness on the part of the
person making the correction, not forced or coerced, not out of lack of
alternatives other than making the correction. The element of choice is a
vital component of the definition of self-correction.

Let me supply a few missing details to those who applauded Li’s
characterization of 64 years of China’s one-party system as one of serial
self-corrections. Between 1949 and 2012, there have been six top leaders
of the CCP. Of these six, two were abruptly and unceremoniously forced out
of power (and one of the two was dismissed without any due process even
according to CCP’s own procedures). A third leader fell from power and was
put under house arrest for 15 years until his death. That is 3 strikes out
of 6 who did not exit power on their intended terms. Two of Mao’s anointed
successors died on the job, one in a fiery plane crash when he tried to
escape to the Soviet Union and the other tortured to death and buried with
a fake name. Oh, did I mention that 30 million people were estimated to
have died from Mao’s disastrous Great Leap Forward, and probably millions
of people died from the violence of the Cultural Revolution? Also, do you
know that Mao not only persisted in but accelerated his Great Leap Forward
policies after the evidence of the extent of famine became crystal-clear?

Li calls the policy changes after these wrenching tumults
“self-corrections.” His reasoning is that an entity called the CCP, but
not anybody else, introduced these policy changes. First of all, doesn’t
that have something to do with the fact that nobody else was allowed a
chance to make those policy changes? Secondly, this fixation on who made
the policy changes rather than on the circumstances under which the policy
changes were made is surely problematic. Let’s extend Li’s logic a little
bit further. Shall we rephrase the American Independence Movement as a
self-correction by the British? Or maybe the ceding of the British
imperial authority over India as another British self-correcting act?
Shall we re-label the Japanese surrender to end the Second World War a
self-correction by the Japanese? Yes, there were two atomic bombs dropped
on Hiroshima and Nagasaki and all of that, but didn’t the representatives
of Emperor Hirohito sign the Japanese Instrument of Surrender on the
battleship of USS Missouri?

To a hammer, everything is a nail. Li sees ills of democracies everywhere
— financial crises in Europe and the United States, money politics and
corruption. I readily agree that money politics in America is a huge
problem and that it is indeed making the system utterly dysfunctional. But
let’s be very clear about exactly how and why money politics is
dysfunctional. It is dysfunctional precisely because it is fundamentally
antithetical to democracy.  Money politics is a perversion of democracy.
It undermines and invalidates a canonical pillar of democracy — one
person, one vote. To be logically consistent, Li should celebrate money
politics because it is moving the United States in the direction of the
authoritarian way of politics that he is so enamored of.

This may be a shocking revelation to Li, but US and European democracies
did not patent financial crisis. Many authoritarian regimes experienced
catastrophic financial and economic crises. Think of Indonesia in 1997 and
the multiple junta regimes in Latin America in the 1970s and the 1980s.
The only authoritarian regimes that go without suffering an explicit
financial crisis are centrally planned economies, such as Romania and East
Germany. But this is entirely because they failed to meet a minimum
condition for having a financial crisis — having a financial system. The
consequences for this defect are well-known — in lieu of sharp cyclical
ups and downs, these countries produced long-term economic stagnations. A
venture capitalist would not fare well in that system.

Li claims that he has studied the ability of democracies to deliver
performance. At least in his talk, the evidence that he has done so is not
compelling. There is no evidence that countries pay an economic price for
being democratic. (It is also important to note that there is no
compelling global evidence that democracies necessarily outperform
autocracies in economic growth either. Some do and some do not. The
conclusion is case by case.) But in the areas of public services, the
evidence is in favor of democracies. Two academics, David Lake and Matthew
Baum, show that democracies are superior to authoritarian countries in
providing public services, such as health and education. Not just
established democracies do a better job; countries that transitioned to
democracies experienced an immediate improvement in the provision of these
public services, and countries that reverted back to authoritarianism
typically suffered a setback.

Li blames low growth in Europe and in the United States on democracy. I
can understand why he has this view, because this is a common mistake
often made by casual observers — China is growing at 8 or 9 percent and
the US is growing at 1 or 2 percent . He is mistaking a mathematical
effect of lower growth due to high base with a political effect of
democracies suppressing growth. Because democratic countries are typically
richer and have much higher per-capita GDP, it is much harder for them to
grow at the same rate as poor — and authoritarian — countries with a lower
level of per-capita GDP. Let me provide an analogy. A 15-year-old boy is
probably more likely to go to see a movie or hang out with his friends on
his own than a 10-year-old because he is older and more mature. It is also
likely that he will not grow as fast as a 10-year-old because he is nearer
to the plateau of human height. It would be foolish to claim, as Li’s
logic basically did, that the 15-year-old is growing more slowly because
he is going to movies on his own.

Li is very clear that he dislikes democracy, more than about the reasons
why he dislikes democracy. Li rejects democracy on cultural grounds. In
his speech, he asserts that democracy is an alien concept for Chinese
culture. This view is almost amusing if not for its consequential
implications. Last time I checked, venture capital is a foreign concept
but that apparently has not stopped Li from practicing and prospering from
it. (And I presume “Eric” to be foreign in origin? I may be wrong on
this.) Conversely, would Li insist on adhering to every and each precept
of Chinese culture and tradition? Would Li object to abolishing the
practice of bound feet of Chinese women?

The simple fact is that the Chinese have accepted many foreign concepts
and practices already. (Just a reminder: Marxism to the Chinese is as
Western as Adam Smith.) It is a perfectly legitimate debate about which
foreign ideas and practices China ought to accept, adopt or adapt, but
this debate is about which ideas China should adopt, not whether China
should adopt any foreign ideas and practices at all.

If the issue is about which ideas or which practices to adopt or reject,
then, unlike Li, I do not feel confident enough to know exactly which
foreign ideas and practices 1.3 billion Chinese people want to embrace or
want to reject. A cultural argument against democracy does not logically
lead to making democracy unavailable to the Chinese but to a course of
actions for the Chinese people themselves to decide on the merits or the
demerits of democracy. Furthermore, if the Chinese themselves reject
democracy on their own, isn’t it redundant to expend massive resources to
fight and suppress democracy? Aren’t there better ways to spend this money?

So far this debate has not occurred in China, because having this debate
in the first place requires some democracy. But it has occurred in other
Chinese environments, and the outcome of those debates is that there is
nothing fundamentally incompatible between Chinese culture and democracy.
Hong Kong, although without an electoral democratic system, has press
freedom and rule of law, and there is no evidence that the place has
fallen into chaos and anarchy. Taiwan today has a vibrant democracy, and
many mainland travelers to Taiwan often marvel that Taiwanese society is
not only democratic but also far more adherent to Chinese traditions than
mainland China. (I have always felt that those who believe that democracy
and Chinese culture are incompatible are closet supporters of Taiwanese
independence. They exclude Taiwanese as Chinese.)

Indeed Li himself has accepted quite a few political reforms that are
normally considered as “Western.” NGOs are okay and even some press
freedom is okay. He also endorses some intra-party democracy. These are
all sensible steps toward making the Chinese system more democratic than
the Maoist system, and I am all for them. The difference is that I see
freedom to vote and multi-party competition as natural and logical
extensions of these initial reforms, whereas Li draws a sharp line in the
sand between the political reforms that have already occurred and the
potential political reforms that some of us have advocated. As much as I
tried, I fail to see any differences in principle between these partial
reforms and the more complete reforms encompassing democracy.

There is a very curious way Li objects to democracy: He objects to many of
the mechanics of democracy. In particular, he has a thing against voting.
But the problem is that voting is simply a way to implement the practice
of democracy, and even Li endorses some democracy. For example, he favors
intra-party democracy. Fine, I do too; but how do you implement
intra-party democracy without voting? This is a bit like praising tennis
as a sport but condemning the use of a racket to play it.

Li has not provided a coherent and logical argument for his positions on
democracy. I suspect, although I do not have any direct evidence, that
there is a simple modus operandi — endorsing reforms the CCP has endorsed
and opposing reforms that CCP has opposed. This is fine as far as
posturing goes but it is not a principled argument of anything.

That said, I believe it is perfectly healthy and indeed essential to have
a rigorous debate on democracy — but that debate ought to be based on
data, facts, logic and reasoning. By this criterion, Li’s talk does not
start that debate.

In this aspect, however, democracy and autocracy are not symmetrical. In a
democracy, we can debate and challenge democracy and autocracy alike, as
Li did when he put down George W. Bush (which I greatly enjoyed) and as I
do here. But those in an autocracy can challenge democracy only.
(Brezhnev, upon being informed that there were protesters shouting “Down
with Reagan” in front of the White House and that the US government could
not do anything to them, reportedly told Reagan, “There are people
shouting ‘Down with Reagan’ on Red Square and I am not doing anything to
them.”) I have no troubles with people challenging people in power and
being skeptical about democracy. In fact, the ability to do so in a
democracy is the very strength of democracy, and a vital source of human
progress. Copernicus was Copernicus because he overturned, not because he
re-created, Ptolemaic astronomy. But by the same criterion, I do have
troubles with people who do not see the merit of extending the same
freedom they have to those who currently do not have it.

Like Li, I do not like the messianic tone some have invoked to support
democracy. I support democracy on pragmatic grounds. The single most
important benefit of democracy is its ability to tame violence. In The
Better Angels of Our Nature, Pinker provided these startling statistics:
During the 20th century, totalitarian regimes were responsible for 138
million deaths, of which 110 million occurred in communist countries.
Authoritarian regimes caused another 28 million deaths. Democracies killed
2 million, mainly in their colonies as well as with food blockades and
civilian bombings during the wars. Democracies, as Pinker pointed out,
have trouble even bringing themselves to execute serial murderers.
Democracies, Pinker argued, have “a tangle of institutional restraints, so
a leader can’t just mobilize armies and militias on a whim to fan out over
the country and start killing massive numbers of citizens.”

Contrary to what he was apparently told when he was a Berkeley hippie, the
idea of democracy is not that it leads to a nirvana but that it can help
prevent a living hell. Democracy has many, many problems. This insurance
function of democracy — of mitigating against disasters — is often
forgotten or taken for granted, but it is the single most important reason
why democracy is superior to every other political system so far invented
by human beings. Maybe one day there will be a better system than
democracy, but the Chinese political system, in Li’s rendition, is not one
of them.

Yasheng Huang is a Professor of Political Economy and International
Management at the MIT Sloan School of Management and is the Founder of
both the China Lab and India Lab at MIT Sloan. His writings have appeared
in The Guardian 
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2009/may/17/china-economy-global-c
risis>, Foreign Policy, Forbes
<http://www.forbes.com/2010/06/15/forbes-india-yasheng-huang-growth-and-fre
edom-opinions-ideas-10-huang.html>, and most recently inForeign Affairs,
where he tangled with Eric X. Li on a similar topic
<http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/138476/eric-x-li/the-life-of-the-pa
rty>. In 2011, Huang spoke at TEDGlobal
<http://www.ted.com/talks/yasheng_huang.html?v2=0> on democracy and growth
in China and India.



More information about the MCLC mailing list